Centenary Special 1913-2012
F
rom Volume 101 No. 1 Spring 2013
One Hundred Years of Philosophy
By George MacDonald Ross
It
is a great honour to be invited to address The Philosophical Society of
England on the occasion of its centenary. By coincidence, it is exactly
half a century since I myself started studying philosophy at university.
It is also just over half a century since the publication of John
Passmore's lengthy and magisterial A
Hundred Years of Philosophy, in 1957. Now, I shall not attempt to
emulate Passmore's achievement by covering a hundred years of
philosophical development in detail, but nevertheless it is possible to
make a number of broad generalisations about major changes in the
philosophical scene since 1912.
A useful starting point is a famous little book first published in the
year the society was founded. This is Bertrand Russell's The Problems of Philosophy. The
work has a number of significant features. One is that, along with most
of the many other books published by him and other leading philosophers
at the time, it was written in a way that would be comprehensible and
interesting to the intelligent lay public. Works directed solely towards
fellow academics, such as Whitehead and Russell's Principia Mathematica, were the
exception rather than the rule. Recall that in 1912, the number of
professional philosophers was minute in comparison with today, and most
of the readers of philosophical books were outside the university
system.
Nowadays, we are used to the idea that, from the Renaissance onwards,
most philosophical debate and innovative thinking took place outside the
academy. Most of us would be hard-pressed to name any significant
European philosopher before Kant who held a university post. It was
really only towards the end of the 19th century that reformed
universities took over from the coffee houses and voluntary clubs as the
centres of gravity of philosophical and scientific activity. The
evolution was very gradual, and even after the beginning of the
twentieth century, at least outside Oxford and Cambridge, there were
still flourishing clubs and societies which eclipsed what was happening
in the struggling new universities.
Consider the example of the Philosophy Department at the University of
Leeds. It celebrated its centenary in 1991, while I was Head of
Department, and I did some research into how it had changed over the
past century. In its early years, it had only one professor and then an
assistant, and most of its few students were destined to become either
school teachers or vicars. The syllabus was narrow, consisting mainly of
some history of philosophy, logic and scientific method, and psychology
(which had not yet established itself as a separate discipline). It
seems that over the years, the Leeds Department did not provide a
fertile environment for philosophical innovation, and I was unable to
unearth any significant product of philosophical research by any member
of staff in the first half century of its existence. The earliest figure
of any note was Stephen Toulmin in the 1950s.
By contrast, the City of Leeds had a flourishing subscription library,
with a more extensive collection of books than the university. It had a
Philosophical and Literary Society with its own premises (though we
should bear in mind that in those days the term 'philosophical' embraced
science as much as philosophy as we now know it). And most
significantly, there was an organisation called the Leeds Arts Club,
which was as much concerned with philosophy as with the arts. One of its
leading lights, Alfred Orage, was primarily responsible for bringing
Nietzsche's philosophy to the attention of the British public at the
beginning of the twentieth century. This was a far greater achievement
than anything produced by the academic philosophers.
During the twentieth century, the academy grew and grew, and virtually
monopolised intellectual life. Philosophical clubs were increasingly
marginalised, and non-academics were effectively barred from publishing
in academic journals or presses. My own father was a product of the free
intellectual world of the early twentieth century. Although he was a
civil servant by profession, he had the mind-set of an academic both in
classics (which he studied at Oxford) and in theology. In his later
years he encountered many obstacles to participating in scholarly
debate, simply because he was not a card-carrying academic. He was
eventually prevented from attending international theological
conferences which were for academics only, and he had great difficulty
publishing a well-argued article on the myth of Atlantis (eventually
accepted, to its credit, by a journal run from the University of
Durham). It is, of course, perfectly reasonable for journals to have
procedures to protect themselves from the effusions of lunatic
amateurs; but peer reviewing already does this. It is a shame that
insistence on university affiliation reinforces an intellectual
apartheid between academics and the scholarly public.
However, this intellectual apartheid does not mean that the
universities constitute a complete philosophical monopoly; but rather
that there are two separate philosophical cultures, with relatively
little interaction. The Philosophical Society of England is a shining
example of an organisation dedicated to promoting the study of
philosophy among the general public, without letting itself become
dominated by academic philosophers (unlike the Royal Institute of
Philosophy, for instance).
One of the differences between modern British culture and that of much
of Europe is that philosophy is not a compulsory school subject. Cynics
may say that making a subject compulsory at school is the surest way of
putting people off it for life. Yet for many it does have a lasting
positive influence, and it makes for a critical mass of people wishing
to continue reading and discussing philosophy. The nearest it ever came
to being compulsory (in England) was during the lifetime of the Higher
School Certificate (from 1918 to 1951), usually taken at 18, which
included a compulsory exam in logic, taken in a reasonably broad sense.
In Scotland, by comparison, philosophy was a compulsory subject in all
the universities, if not in schools, until the latter part of the
twentieth century. In the same spirit as the Higher School Certificate,
the International Baccalaureate includes a compulsory course on Theory
of Knowledge, as well as having an option of Philosophy as one of the
main subjects of study.
It is true that for a number of decades now it has been possible to
study philosophy at A level (examinations usually studied between the
ages of 16 and 18); but the number of students has always been too small
to have a significant cultural impact. The syllabus has tended to be
very similar to that of first-year university courses, which may explain
why many academic philosophers have been hostile to it — indeed at some
universities admissions tutors even refused to accept it as a valid
qualification at all. Interestingly, there was a lively debate about
philosophy teaching in the press at the time of the World Congress of
Philosophy at Brighton in 1988. Some philosophers, such as Roger
Scruton, argued that 16 was too young an age to start studying
philosophy — even though this was perhaps the age at which Theaetetus
started discussing philosophy with Socrates, but far younger than
Plato's extreme view that one should not start philosophy until the age
of fifty. In my opinion, you are never too young to be encouraged to
think philosophically, and it is arguable that you shouldn't start later
than the age of entry to secondary school, when students begin to become
less creative, and more inflexible in their thinking styles.
Doubtless this is part of the thinking behind a growing movement
called Philosophy for Children. It was originally set up in the 1980s
in the USA by Matthew Lipman (1922-2010), and it has inspired similar
organisations in other countries, including the UK. Its approach could
hardly be more different from that of the A level. The A level is quite
didactic, with approved texts specifying a defined range of possible
answers to an equally defined range of traditional philosophical
issues. It is a back-handed compliment to the authors of such texts
that it is perfectly possible for candidates to get high grades in the
exams simply by memorising their contents. That said, I hasten to add
that there are innumerable examples of excellent philosophy teaching in
sixth forms, despite the structural rigidities of the A level syllabus
and marking schemes.
By contrast, Philosophy for Children is dialogic, open-ended, and
non-assessed, encouraging students to think independently and
imaginatively, and to discuss issues co-operatively. Lipman's method
involves the students reading novelettes about philosophical issues
targeted at different age groups from early primary upwards. The
students themselves raise questions about what they have read, and there
are strict rules as to how they conduct philosophical debate — such as
always taking on board what the previous speaker has said, giving
reasons in support of any assertion, being courteous and not
interrupting, and so on. I once observed a discussion among young
schoolchildren at a comprehensive school in a deprived area which was
far more civilised, co-operative, reasoned, and imaginative than the
typical discussion among university students of philosophy with high A
level scores. Proponents of philosophy for children do not always use
Lipman's materials as such, but all agree that the aim is to stimulate
philosophical enquiry and debate by one means or another, rather than
lecturing students about what professional philosophers have achieved.
In recent times, the methods of philosophy for children have been
extended to adults through the community philosophy initiative, which
holds that many of society's problems can be solved, or at least
mitigated, if adults causing these problems can be helped to
conceptualise their situation philosophically, and to engage in rational
debate with others. This is closely related to cognitive behaviour
therapy, which is a modern version of the ancient belief in philosophy
as a method for helping people to overcome psychological problems and
achieve a good life.
If we add into the picture the recent growth of cafés philosophiques and pub
philosophy, and of philosophical magazines directed towards the general
public, I believe that lay philosophy is in a far healthier state than
it was a few decades ago. Nevertheless, there is still a serious divide
between the philosophy of the people and the philosophy of the
academics, with very little crossover between the two.
To return to Russell's Problems of
Philosophy, there is another characteristic feature that
distinguishes the practice of philosophy in the early twentieth century
from current practice. This is that Russell confronts significant
philosophical issues directly, and refers to major figures of the past
only indirectly when relevant. Along with other British philosophers of
the early and middle twentieth century, such as A. J. Ayer, Ludwig
Wittgenstein, and Gilbert Ryle, he writes without footnotes or a
bibliography. A hundred years later, this would be quite unacceptable in
academic writing, and we need to consider why.
Comparing an early twentieth-century philosophical text with an early
twenty-first century one, the most obvious difference is that the latter
is full of references to what other writers have written about a
problem, at the expense of addressing the problem itself. Every claim
has to be supported by a reference, even if it is totally unclear what
the reader should do about the reference. Reading all the works referred
to in a single article could take years, and the further references in
these works a whole lifetime. But if you are not expected to read the
references, what are they there for? Their sole function seems to be as
an authority for the statement made.
When I was a student, I was taught that the argument from authority was
one of the great fallacies in human reasoning. To appeal to an authority
was an abandonment of empirical experience and logic as the criteria of
truth. Of course we have to trust others a lot of the time; but when we
are doing philosophy, we need to rationally evaluate what others have said on
the matter in hand.
There is a widely held myth that scholastic philosophers were
especially prone to the argument from authority — that they clinched
every argument with 'The philosopher saith . . .', i.e. an appeal to the
authority of Aristotle. But this is quite misleading. If you look at a
classic work of scholastic philosophy, such as Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologiae, you will see that
his method is first to define a problem, then to list the solutions to
it proposed by different authors, and finally, and most importantly, to
give reasons for preferring one solution to the others, or opting for
some compromise position. This seems to me an excellent model for how
references should be used.
Nonetheless, perhaps it was a fear of appearing to be like a scholastic
philosopher that led to a modern philosophical culture, from Descartes
and Hobbes to the middle of the twentieth century, with authors such as
Russell, Wittgenstein, Ryle and others, which erred on the side of
failure to give adequate acknowledgment of the views of others. So why
was there a marked shift from giving too few references to giving too
many? One possible factor is that, until quite late in the century, it
was common for people to be appointed to academic posts in philosophy
without having produced a doctoral (PhD) thesis. When I was a student,
only a minority of my teachers had a PhD, and most of those were from
abroad. I was firmly told that an Oxbridge BA was a licentia docendi, or a licence to
teach, and that the reason why Oxford introduced the postgraduate BPhil
(and not, note, the DPhil) as a teaching qualification was because
philosophy was only a small proportion of what was studied there at
undergraduate level (whereas the Cambridge Moral Sciences Tripos was a
single-honours programme).
The reason why this is relevant is because the PhD thesis is now an
academic's first and most formative experience of extensive
philosophical writing. The requirement that the thesis must be original
means that the author must give evidence that no one else has published
the views contained in the thesis. The only way of providing this
evidence is to trawl all the relevant literature, and to show that
nothing is the same as the substance of the thesis. Journal editors and
publishers have a similar interest in originality and avoidance of
plagiarism, so it is in effect a necessary condition of publication that
books and articles have copious bibliographies and footnotes. The
requirements for a PhD thus become a lifetime habit.
Another reason for the change is the pressure to publish. Until the
early twentieth century, the idea of a university was of an institution
of which the primary purpose was to teach undergraduates. For example,
one of the central themes of Cardinal Newman's much mentioned but little
read The Idea of a University
is that teaching and research are distinct and incompatible activities,
and that they should be carried out in separate institutions. In the
first two decades of the twentieth century, at the University of Leeds,
for example, even the scientists and engineers amongst the academics had
to obtain special permission to undertake research projects, in case
they detracted from the teaching for which they were paid. Research and
writing for publication were regarded as spare-time activities or even
hobbies, and philosophy teachers published only if they felt they had
something important to say. It was not really until after the First
World War that research began to be seen as part of the duties of an
academic, and not until much later that it began to be monitored.
The really big change in the UK took place in 1986, with the first
Research Assessment Exercise (RAE), now rebranded as the Research
Excellence Framework (REF). This came about because the then
polytechnics complained that they received less funding per student than
the universities. The universities responded by saying that part of
their mission was to conduct blue-skies research (i.e. not just
particular projects funded by sponsors), and that the difference in
income was accounted for by the time academics spent on research rather
than just teaching. The Treasury then called their bluff by insisting
that they should account for the research activity of every member of
academic staff — and hence the RAE came about. It initially measured the
quantity of publications, but later became more qualitative. Certainly,
the amount of money involved put immense pressure on universities to
ensure that everyone produced as much as possible and within a short
timescale.
Since the exercise covered all academic disciplines, considerations of
equity meant that, as far as possible, the same general criteria would
apply. Significantly, works intended for the general public or students
simply did not count, and in some departments staff were explicitly
forbidden to write such works. This is one reason why so many textbooks
are written by American rather than British academics. Of course, there
is a grey area where a book might be considered to be both for the lay
and for the academic market, as usually used to be the case. But the
tendency is to play safe, and make sure that anything published is
unmistakably an academic research publication. This means that, in
philosophy, the style of writing has become more like that of other
disciplines, such as sociology, which is notorious for its excessive and
uncritical reliance on references.
I was involved in discussions as to what would count as a research
publication on teaching methods for RAE purposes, and whether it would
be assessed by the Education Panel or the relevant subject panel, when I
was Director of the Subject Centre for Philosophical and Religious
Studies of the Higher Education Academy. The main criterion that emerged
was that a work should be 'embedded in the literature' to count as
research — i.e. that it should refer to lots of works on the same
topic. Personal experience and reasoned arguments didn't count. This
concerned me, because, until the Subject Centre started publishing its
own journal, there was almost no published literature on the teaching of
philosophy to refer to. No-one wanted to listen when I pointed out that
anyone doing research in an entirely new field would be excluded from
the RAE because of lack of references. To put it another way,
publications that are heavily derivative from the work of others count
as research, whereas entirely original research does not count at all!
It has been observed that academics in general have a tendency to
discuss each others' writings rather than directly confronting issues
themselves. Academics live off the oxygen of publicity, and like nothing
better than being referred to, whether in agreement or not. So to
outsiders academia looks like a closed club for mutual appreciation. Or
perhaps I should say a collection of clubs, because the past century has
seen a vast increase in the degree of specialisation as well as in the
quantity of publications. So much is published that no-one can keep up
with the literature in more than one sub-discipline. This is as true of
philosophy as of any other subject, and philosophers tend to define
themselves as metaphysicians, logicians, ethicists and so on. rather
than just as philosophers.
Indeed, there is now also a host of 'philosophy ofs', such as
philosophy of education, philosophy of science, and so on, which have
relatively little commonality with mainstream philosophy. Noel Malcolm,
a distinguished Hobbes scholar, left academia for a while to write a
weekly political column for the Spectator (he told me that it gave him
more time for research than being an academic). He once wrote a very
amusing piece on the oversupply of academic writing, saying that he no
longer had time to read all that was written about Hobbes, let alone the
history of philosophy or philosophy itself in general. He concluded that
instead of encouraging academics to produce more and more, the powers
that be should take a leaf out of the book of the European Union, and
pay academics set-aside money for books they refrained from writing.
Another factor which makes philosophy different from most other
disciplines is that the very concept of research doesn't seem
appropriate for what philosophers do. Research involves the discovery of
something unknown, whereas what philosophers do is to reconceptualise
and assess the significance of things that are already known. This may
lie behind the slowness of philosophers to adopt the PhD as an essential
qualification, or to come to see publication as part of the job, and
not just a hobby. Now that the concept of philosophical research has
been accepted, there is a tendency for it to become more like research
in other disciplines. In particular, there is the scientistic expectation that
effective research will lead to positive and objective results.
Transferred to philosophy, this implies that there is objective
philosophical truth which can be arrived at by research. In other words,
it implies what a sceptic would call dogmatic philosophy.
In the history of philosophy, scepticism has come in and out of
fashion. It was alive and well in the ancient world, with Socrates
(arguably), Pyrrho, and Sextus Empiricus. It lay low in the middle ages,
perhaps because of church control over the universities. After its
revival in the Renaissance, especially under Montaigne, it was well
represented in the modern period, with strong tendencies in Locke and
Berkeley, and the overt scepticism of Hume and Kant. During the past
hundred years, the logical positivists, while deferential to physical
science, were dogmatically sceptical about metaphysics, ethics,
aesthetics, and theology.
Similarly, linguistic philosophers rejected anything not expressible in
ordinary language, and, in his later writings, Wittgenstein treated
philosophy as a disease to be cured. But since then, scepticism seems to
have gone out of fashion, and philosophy is largely conducted
dogmatically, in the sense that practitioners of the sub-disciplines
believe that they have arrived at objective truths, which they can then
share with fellow-academics and students. One of the indications of this
shift is the revival of sub-disciplines, in particular metaphysics,
which were once considered taboo, but are now hailed as peaks of
excellence in some departments. For some earlier twentieth-century
philosophers, this would be the equivalent of a reversion to alchemy in
a chemistry department, or to astrology in an astronomy department.
There has also been a change in attitude towards the applicability of
philosophy. At the beginning of the last century, people like Russell
and Joad believed passionately in the usefulness of philosophy for
ordinary people, both as an approach to thinking, and in its
applicability to morality and philosophy of life. Russell in particular
wrote many books and made broadcasts on topics such as marriage,
happiness, idleness, and politics; and I am sure he believed he could
write them only by virtue of being a philosopher. It is thanks to
Russell and his like that prominent philosophers had a much higher
status and respect in British society than they have today.
In some respects, philosophy has tended to withdraw into itself, and
some philosophers boast that their discipline is studied for its own
sake without any practical application. At the World Congress in
Brighton in 1988, which I mentioned earlier, Allen Phillips Griffiths
was quoted in the press as saying that 'Philosophy butters no parsnips',
by which he meant that it had no practical application. Shamelessly,
the undergraduate handbook of the Philosophy Department of the
University of Leeds once had a statement right at the beginning that
studying philosophy was entirely irrelevant to a career. A number of
university administrations are exasperated by the difficulty of getting
philosophers to articulate the useful intellectual skills philosophy
students develop in the course of their studies. In fact, When I did
this for my own department, my colleagues complained that fostering
these skills was not the aim of a philosophical education — which of
course is true, but that doesn't mean that they aren't a useful
by-product of studying philosophy.
The big exception to the denial of the usefulness of philosophy is
applied ethics. Half a century ago, the general assumption was that
ethicists studied the logic of moral discourse (what is now called
'meta-ethics'), but qua philosophers they had nothing to say about what
is or is not moral. That was dubbed 'casuistry', or the resolving of
particular moral issues, and it was the job of priests and politicians.
Philosophy might help people think more clearly, but it was ultimately
up to the individual to decide what was right or wrong.
In recent years, the sub-discipline of applied ethics has undergone
spectacular growth. It has been helped in particular by the requirement
of various professions, especially the medical profession, that trainees
should study ethics. Non-philosophers probably expect the training to
consisting in learning and applying a code of conduct. In fact what
trainees get is help in thinking more effectively about issues in the
practice of their profession, in the light of traditional theories about
the nature of morality. Consistently with the assumptions of the
previous century, applied ethicists do not see themselves as having a
licence to preach to their students what their moral values should be.
Having devoted much of my professional career to trying to bring about
improvements in the teaching of philosophy at UK universities, I would
have liked to end my talk with an account of the ways in which the
teaching of philosophy has got better . Unfortunately, apart from a few
shining examples of improved practice, methods of teaching and
assessment have remained largely unchanged over the past century. This
is surprising, because one would expect teaching methods to reflect the
prevailing fashion in views as to the nature of philosophy. In
particular, a scepticism about the possibility of peculiarly
philosophical knowledge might be sympathetic to a student-centred and
dialogic approach, as practised by Socrates. On the other hand, a belief
in the objectivity of metaphysics might favour the didactic lecture
followed by an unseen sat examination testing the student's memory. But
the latter method has largely prevailed over the past century and more,
despite changes in belief about the nature of philosophy.
In all this I am reminded of the remark by an American university
principal that scientists who are meticulous about doing nothing without
the backing of experimental evidence in the practice of their research,
completely ignore the empirical evidence about what is or is not
effective when it comes to their teaching. I fear that much the same is
true of university philosophers. You would have thought that
philosophers of all people would be reflective about what they do, but I
have seen no philosophical defence of the practice of teaching
philosophy through lectures and assessing it through sat exams.
So my conclusion is that congratulations must be offered to
organisations such as the Philosophical Society of England, but more
generally, the world of academic philosophy needs to do much more to put
its house in order.
Contact details:
George MacDonald Ross, School of Philosophy, Religion and the History of
Science, University of Leeds, UK
email
< G.M.Ross@leeds.ac.uk>
This is a revised
version of the paper presented to the Malmesbury Conference of 2012, as
part of the Philosophical Society of England's Centenary Celebrations.
Comments
Post a Comment
Our authors very much value feedback from readers. Unfortunately, there is so much spam on the internet now that we now have to moderate posts on the older articles. Please accept our apologies for any extra time this may require of you.