From The Philosopher, Volume LXXXXIX No. 1
PLATO’S CAVE
and the Bicameral Brain
By Jim Danaher
Throughout most of our Western history,
and especially our modern history, during which 'mathematics and
everything akin to mathematics' has exercised an hypnotic appeal
against which we have had the most difficulty resisting.
Modernity became obsessed with analysis and the elimination of
vague, ambiguous, or contradictory ideas. We fell almost completely
under its sway and came to imagine that the picture of reality that
such thinking provided gave us the best way to understand our world and
our place in it.
It was as if we had finally found our way out of the cave and
into the kind of light that Plato had thought existed with the Platonic
forms. It appeared that modern thinkers had found their way out of the
shadowy and mysterious realm of our actual experience and found the
kind of certainty that Plato had sought.
Today, however, we are able to see that from a very different
perspective because of what we know concerning the human brain. We now
know that as appealing as such certainty is, it merely represents one
way that the human brain is capable of thinking. Instead of the moving
picture of our actual experience, we are capable of ideas that
represent snap shots, which make the distances, perspectives, and
relations that we actually experience appear fixed and give us the kind
of clear and distinct ideas that we crave.
Until recently, it was easy to fall under the sway of such
analytic, abstract thinking and imagine it gave us the best way to
truth and was therefore synonymous with reason itself. We now know,
however, that such a mode of reason is merely one way we have of
thinking about our world and ourselves. We now know that our desire for
clear and distinct ideas, which began with Plato and culminated in the
Cartesianism of Modernity, was merely one way we are able to think
about the world, and although it gives us the kind of certainty that
makes us feel divine, it does not give us a very realistic picture of
our human experience.
* * * * *
In the seventh book of the
Republic, Plato sets forth
his famous allegory of the cave. The traditional understanding
interpreted it as Plato arguing that both becoming and being were real
because there were two different worlds or realms of reality. One was
the world of sense-data, which the Pre-Socratic philosopher, Heraclitus
argued was purely a matter of becoming. In this world, nothing ever
exists in a pure state of being but is always becoming something
else.
Plato however, claimed that there was another world where
things did exist in a pure state of being. Parmenides and several other
Pre-Socratic philosophers had long claimed that the world of which
Heraclitus spoke was an illusory world produced by a naïve trust
in our unreliable senses and that in fact reason showed us that only
being truly existed and all becoming and change was illusory. Plato
agreed with both Heraclitus and Parmenides: he believed that the world
of our sense data was real and not merely illusory, but there was also
a world of pure being - the parallel universe that Plato would come to
describe as the world of the forms.
Since we have ideas of things that were eternal and
unchanging, quintessentially geometirical andmathemematical concepts
such as numbers or the idea of a circle as a figure with every point
equal distance from the center, Plato believed that such entities must
be more real than the temporal and mutable things we experience in the
world of our senses.
Everything that we call a circle in the world of our senses is
never the real circle or a figure whose every point is perfectly equal
distance from the center. It is only a mutable replica of that eternal
and immutable idea of a circle. Plato further imagined that if there
were things as perfect as asuch eternal and immutable ideas of things
like a circle, perhaps there were also eternal, immutable, and perfect
ideas of courage, justice, love, or virtue - the instances of which
appear in this world of our senses as mere shadowy replicas.
But what kind of thing is this parallel univese? Plato set us
on a course to overcome the ambiguous and vague ideas that arise out of
our experience and discover clear and distinct ideas by which we might
organize our understanding. He further imagined that since such clear
and distinct ideas were very different from those that arise out of our
experience in this world of sense-data, there must be another world
that houses these immutable and eternal ideas upon which we desire to
found our understanding.
Although Plato spoke of another world that housed these
eternal and immutable forms, and we equally have interpreted him in
those terms for centuries, today we are open to a very different
reading of Plato. That is because we now understand that what we
naively attribute to the world outside of ourselves is often more a
matter of how we think about the world than how the world actually is.
Since the time of Kant, philosophy has stressed that we bring
much more to our experience of the world than we had previously
thought. Furthermore, in the two centuries following Kant, we have come
to discover that what we bring to our experience is much more than the
innate mental hardware that Kant imagined.
We now accept that we interpret our experience through
linguistic concepts that are culturally and historically relative.
Perhaps creatures without language, culture, or history perceive their
experience as given, but human beings certainly should not.
Once we realize how relative our understanding is to our own
culture, history, and language community, we become much more
philosophical. Reality is no longer simply data that we experience but
an interpretation that is open to reinterpretation given different
cultural and historical concepts. As we gain ever-greater insight into
our human condition, those insights provide interpretations not
available to previous generations. One such insight concerns what we
have recently come to understand about the nature of our bicameral
brains.
Since at least the time of the Greeks, we have known that the
human brain is composed of both a left and right hemisphere. Today, our
advanced technology has brought us to a much better understanding of
the two hemispheres and the way they function. With functional magnetic
resonance imaging, neuroscientists think that they are able to see how
the different parts of the brain respond to different types of stimulus
and thus involve different types of thinking. One thing that they say they have found is that although the two hemispheres certainly work together, they alternate in dominance with different types of thinking.
In a book on
The Physiology of Behavior, Neil Carlson says:
In general the left hemisphere
participates in the analysis of information . . . In contrast, the
right hemisphere is specialized for synthesis; it is particularly good
at putting isolated elements together to perceive things as wholes.
The consensus today is that we are naturally equipped with two very
distinct abilities in terms of how to think about our experience. We
can analyze our experience and break it down into ever-smaller parts,
or we can join the parts of our experience together into ever-greater
wholes. Both modes of thought are within our power and both have a
logic, which governs their reasoning. To prefer one mode of thought to
the exclusion of the other is to limit our rational capacity and leave
us ‘half-witted’. Sadly, much of the Western intellectual tradition has done
just that, focusing on the ‘analytic’ and neglecting the ‘holistic’. We
have come to associate reason itself with left-brain analysis.
What is so attractive about left-brain analysis is that it
divides our objects of thought into ever-smaller parts that eliminate
all contradictions and leave us with clear and distinct ideas. For
example, take any paradoxical or contradictory phenomena and begin to
analyze it into its parts and the contradiction eventually disappears.
Life as a whole, maybe both joyful and sorrowful, but we can analyze it
into sorrowful parts and joyful parts thus eliminating the paradoxes
and contradictions and leaving us with clear and distinct ideas.
Both Plato and Aristotle certainly set us on that course, and
in the interest of establishing such clear and distinct ideas, they
introduced what we have come to know as the Laws of Thought. These laws
of thought include the law of identity
(A equals A), the law of
non-contradiction
(A does not equal not A), and the law of the
excluded middle
(either A or not A, but not both A and not A).
Plato endorses the laws of non-contradiction and excluded middle in the
Republic
where he has Socrates say:
It is obvious that the same thing
will never do or suffer opposites in the same respect in relation to
the same thing and at the same time.
Likewise, in the
Metaphysics, Aristotle says:
The same attribute cannot at the same
time belong and not belong to the same subject and in the same
respect.
Both Plato and Aristotle understood that we naturally encountered
contradictions but we could eliminate them by thinking analytically and
dividing things up into ever-smaller parts until all the contradictions
disappeared. Socrates is a contradiction in that he is both a father
and not a father. We can eliminate that contradiction, however, by
thinking about Socrates at one particular time or in relationship to
one particular person. These are the qualifications that Plato and
Aristotle ascribe above in order to analytically break things down into
ever smaller parts and thereby eliminate contradictions and give us
clear and distinct ideas.
In the modern era, Descartes took this a step further and
convinced us that all clear and distinct ideas are true. This Cartesian
thinking came to have such a hold on the modern mind that we eventually
came to believe that only clear and distinct ideas were true.
Consequently, analytic thinking came to be seen as synonymous with
reason itself and ideas that were vague, ambiguous, or contradictory
simply were not true.
Of course, there had always been an alternative, synthetic way
of thinking that resisted the urge to analyze our experience into
ever-smaller parts but instead leaves things whole and bears the
contradictions and ambiguity that is so much apart of our actual
experience. We can trace That tradition can be traced back to
Heraclitus in the Greek world, and during the Christian period, the
medieval mystics continued to practice such thinking in spite of the
overwhelming influence of Plato and Aristotle. In the modern period, it
found some expression with the Romantic Poets, but it was not until
Hegel that it received a full philosophical explication and the status
of logic.
Just as Plato and Aristotle had developed laws to govern
analytic thinking, Hegel offered laws to govern synthetic thinking.
With synthetic thinking, we deal with the whole rather than the parts,
and when thinking about all the parts or respects together we certainly
encounter contradictions, and the truth is often both/and, rather than
either/or.
For Hegel, Plato and Aristotle’s laws of analytic thinking
were artificial and made 'abstract identity its principle (
Logic, 75).'
When, according to traditional logic, we reason about whether Socrates
was or was not a father, it is not Socrates we are reasoning about but
one aspect of Socrates' life at one particular time. By abstracting one
aspect of Socrates' life, at one particular time, toward one particular
person, we create an abstract idea over which the traditional laws of
thought rule. But when we think about things in their wholeness rather
than as clear and distinct abstract ideas, however, 'everything is
inherently contradictory', says Hegel in his Science, and the
law of contradiction, rather than the law of non-contradiction is the
guiding principle.
Hegel specifically attacked the law of identity, saying that,
'the law of identity says very little in itself'. The fact that
A
equals A is merely a tautology and has little meaning. It tells us
almost nothing about the identity of a thing. The only way a thing
truly takes on identity is through its otherness; that is, by
including in its identity what it is not. Only a thing's otherness
provides the boundaries that give it definition and meaning. Likewise
Hegel also agreed with Heraclitus that since living things are always
becoming, they must contain within themselves that which they are not.
It is one of the
fundamental prejudices of logic as hitherto understood and of ordinary
thinking, that contradiction is not so characteristically essential and
immanent a determination as identity; . . . but contradiction is the
root of all movement and vitality; it is only in so far as something
has a contradiction within it that it moves, has an urge and activity.
A little later, he says something that is even more shocking
to those who strictly adhere to the traditional laws of thought and
imagine them to be universal and the basis of reason itself.
Something moves, not because at one moment it is here and at another
there, but because at one and the same moment it is here and not here,
because in this 'here', it at once is and is not.
This is an obvious contradiction, and the laws of thought
would say that something could not be here and not here at the same
time, but that is only true if we think of time analytically whereby
time moves from one fixed, analyzable point to another (for example,
t1,
t2, t3…), thus constituting a series of present moments. If that is
the nature of time, then Hegel is certainly wrong, since something is
here, for example, at the present moment (for example,
t4) and
not anywhere else. If, however, there are no fixed points on the
continuum that is time, and time, like motion, cannot be arrested
without it becoming something other than time, then Hegel is right and
something is both ‘here’ and ‘not here’ at the same time. To think of
time as an ongoing continuum forces us to think contrary to the laws of
non-contradiction and excluded middle. Like motion or time, living
things, in their livingness, also defy arrest.
Hegel also writes:
Abstract self-identity is not as yet
a livingness....
Something is therefore alive only in so far as it contains
contradictions within it. Yet, of course, we would not want to be
without our ability to reason abstractly. Abstract analysis is
certainly useful when constructing artifices like bridges and
skyscrapers, or when we want to balance our checkbooks, but it is a
grave mistake to believe that such thinking provides the best way to
understand our human condition. The truth is that we are equipped with
the ability to think analytically in order to get clear and distinct
ideas, but we are also able to resist that temptation and bear the
vagueness and ambiguity that so naturally comes with our human
experience.
The challenge is to resist the impulse to believe that one way
of thinking is superior to the other. As Leo Straus says in
What is
Political Philosophy, human beings:
… are constantly attracted and
deluded by two opposite charms: the charm of competence which is
engendered by mathematics and everything akin to mathematics, and the
charm of humble awe, which is engendered by meditation on the human
soul and its experiences. Philosophy is characterized by a gentle, if
firm, refusal to succumb to either charm.
What Plato expressed so long ago with his allegory of the cave was not,
as he imagined, about another world, but rather about the way we desire
to think about our human experience. Not only do we desire to know the
forms so we might organize our understanding correctly, but we want them
to be the kind of clear and distinct ideas we find in geometry.
In the modern period, Descartes convinced us that such a
Platonic ambition was the way to solve all of our problems and
consequently the modern mind came to associate the analytic thinking of
the left-brain as synonymous with reason itself.
Consequently, no contradictory, ambiguous, or vague ideas
could claim to be true. With such thinking, there were no mysteries,
only puzzles that in time we would solve through a single mode of right
thinking. Modern science told us that they had discovered a singular
right way of thinking that if followed would eventually bring us to a
complete understanding of the world and our place within it.
What we now understand much better than both Plato and
Descartes is that we are hard-wired to reason in two very different and
distinct ways: we can think analytically in order to get clear and
distinct ideas and thereby eliminate all ambiguity and vagueness, or we
can leave our experience whole and bear the paradoxes and
contradictions that are so much a part of that actual experience. Plato
might have imagined these as two different worlds but we now have the
benefit of another way to interpret them - not as two universes that
never interact but two distinct ways to think about the same world.
Furthermore, since the human brain provides us with two very
distinct ways of interpreting our experience, there should not be a
question of which is superior to the other. Both are part of our
natural capacity and we should not have to choose one to the exclusion
of the other. The trick is to have a whole mind that is capable of both
modes of reason; that is, that we can think analytically, do
mathematics, and create computers and bridges, but we can also think in
ways that bear the contradictions, vagueness, and ambiguity that is so
much a part of our actual experience.
Address for correspondence:Professor Jim Danaher, <philos1011@gmail.com
Comments
Post a Comment
Our authors very much value feedback from readers. Unfortunately, there is so much spam on the internet now that we now have to moderate posts on the older articles. Please accept our apologies for any extra time this may require of you.